Hey everyone!
Today I’m going to discuss the book I’ve been reading over the
past few weeks! Daniel Gilbert’s Stumbling
on Happiness, while titled like a self-help book about how to find
happiness, instead offers an explanation of what happiness really is and how
the human brain attempts (successfully and otherwise) to maintain it. And in
the face of that lack of success, Gilbert offers a solution that no one takes.
Gilbert asserts that the maintenance of happiness requires the
ability to imagine the potential future. We can’t make decide what would make
us happy without being able to think about how our lives would be after the
choice. However, Gilbert demonstrates that the very process of imagination we
use to make these decisions is very much flawed.
Imagination has three main failings, according to Gilbert. First, we
do not recognize that our imagination “works so quickly, quietly, and
effectively” that we don’t stop to think whether it is accurate (Gilbert, 2006).
Second, we cannot prevent our
imagination from framing in our present situation its projected results. And third,
imagination does a terrible job predicting how we will feel after we make a
decision.
However, Gilbert doesn’t leave us without a solution to the
problem we face when envisioning the results of a decision. All imagination’s
faults can be countered by merely asking someone who is currently experiencing
what we would be trying to imagine. Unfortunately, people prefer to think of
themselves as unique, and consequently discount those people’s feelings
(McFarland & Miller, 1990).
Each of these claims has relevant research to support it, and the
author himself has led several studies cited in the book during his career in
social psychology. Daniel Gilbert is a psychology professor at Harvard University
and has received several awards for his research. Furthermore, many of the
concepts and theories discussed in this course appear in his explanations, which
further demonstrates that he supports his claims with established research.
For example, Gilbert uses the availability
heuristic to explain why we always think that we’re in the slowest checkout
line. When people have to decide how frequent something is, they tend base
their answer on how many examples of it come to mind (Tversky & Kahneman,
1973). Gilbert shows that in the case of checkout lines, those examples are
generally the unusually slow ones, regardless of how many checkout lines we’ve
sped through. Because the slow checkout lines are more memorable for us, we
have more slow examples than average examples from which to base our decision
about what kind of luck we have at the checkout counter.
I knew that Gilbert was an esteemed social psychologist, which was
the first facet to draw my interest to this particular book. I didn’t want a
book from an author I hadn’t heard of or that I wasn’t confident would cite
research. However, I knew that many books on the list met those criteria. So,
after narrowing the pool down somewhat, I selected based on the content.
Happiness has always interested me, so I jumped on the opportunity to read a
book that would focus on it. (At the time of selection, I expected everyone
else to also jump on the opportunity to read this book. Later in the class, I
realized this was an example of the false
consensus effect. Ross, Greene and House (1977) showed that people
typically assume that most people feel the same way that they do. But when I
got there, no one I talked to was even interested in Stumbling on Happiness!)
Ultimately, I’m glad that I read this book. Not only was it full
of interesting information, it was relayed through a type of dry absurdity that
resonates perfectly with my own sense of humor. Psychological concepts would frequently
be followed by examples that were either immediately relatable or incredibly
outlandish, which aided understanding. However, people more serious than me might
find Gilbert’s writing style off-putting.
Aside from stylistic concerns, I believe that both experts and
laypeople would enjoy this book. For me, it applied my knowledge of social
psychology in a new way to an interesting topic. For laypeople, the book
provides the knowledge in an easily understandable way. (Perhaps people with
considerably more knowledge than me will not benefit from reading the book, but
Gilbert has shown me that I cannot actually assume that how I imagine I would
feel in that situation is correct.)
I would have liked it if the author had expanded on the final
section, about how to combat our imagination’s faults. Although I’m sure he
would have put in more strategies if research had uncovered them, I believe
that is part of Gilbert’s point: We can’t easily do it. Even after we learn
about these errors, we still can’t do
it. We don’t pay attention to the problems, and we don’t recognize how much damage
they do, even in hindsight.
And this is as close as I can get to making “Bravado” fit in here,
my favorite Rush song. I picked it weeks ago to appear in this blog, because
the song is about happiness persisting despite constant setbacks. I expected
this book would be about that. Instead, it was about how our imagination does a
terrible job of ensuring our happiness, but damn if I’ll let that stop me from
shoehorning in a great and uplifting song!
We will pay the price (of our faulty imagination), but we will not
count the cost (of how exactly it harms us).
... Close enough.
Now that we’ve had that nice interlude, I’ll provide a personal
example for each of Gilbert’s three main errors of imagination: realism,
presentism, and rationalization.
Gilbert ascribed the error of realism to flaws in memory and
perception. We both add details that we might expect to have been there, and
ignore details that we might not expect. What’s worse, we don’t realize that we’ve
done so, causing us to blindly accept our imagined future at face value. Most
of his examples resonated with me. Except for one.
Gilbert describes a situation where you happily agree to babysit
your friend’s children and look forward to having a fun time with the kids,
until the time arrives and you realize that there’s a lot of work involved. In
other words, you imagine an idealized version of the situation that doesn’t
include any of the gritty details that you would ultimately find unpleasant
(Eyal et. al, 2004).
I spent a long time thinking about it, but could not think of a
single instance when I’ve done that. Whenever I’ve agreed to do a task I’m
familiar with, I’m aware of everything it entails from the start. I can’t
recall a time I’ve felt surprised by the unpleasant details of an experience if
I’d ever done it before. All of the other heuristics brought fairly
uninteresting examples to mind, ones that didn’t seem unique enough to share.
In contrast, I thought it was very interesting that I don’t experience this “universal”
imagination heuristic. Maybe I’m more rational than the average person, but I
think it’s more likely I simply haven’t had the opportunity to experience it
since I started paying attention. Hopefully I’ll be cognizant of this error in
the future. I could say I’d imagine I would, but then I’d be committing the
error of presentism.
When people imagine the future, they do not properly disentangle
it from their present state, hence “presentism” (Gilbert, 2006). So because I’m
currently dwelling on the previous example, I would imagine I would still be
thinking about it months from now. But according to Gilbert, I would be wrong.
Presentism affects large decisions, too. When I first came to
Southwestern, I had not really decided my major. I enjoyed Economics and
Psychology most in high school, so I pursued those here. Upon reflection, those
were the most “scientific” courses I had taken in that they included both
models for predicting behavior and also clear, relatable examples as evidence.
Sure, Rutherfold’s gold foil experiment was interesting, but also too esoteric
to prompt rational thought at the age of 14.
Unfortunately, in an upper level economics class we learned about
a particular theory, the quantity theory of money. It was a simple theory, MV = PQ. The amount of money times the
number of times that money changes hands is equal to the price of the average
widget/employee times the total output. It seems logical enough (actually, I
think I understand the concept better now than I did at the time), but it
required a set of assumptions longer than the set of variables in the equation!
And it turned out that none of those assumptions was ever true. I recall
thinking in class, “what good is this theory, then, if it’s unusable outside of
the classroom?”
That day, my perspective shifted involuntarily, and I lost my ability
to perceive economics as predictive rather than descriptive. I changed that
major to business (which may have ended up being even less useful, but that is
beside the point). This may have been an extreme reaction, but the belief I
held in the present when I decided to take economics was shattered in the future.
Had I been able to predict that I would feel so strongly about that, I would
have not gotten involved in the first place. But instead, my imagination
committed the error of rationalization (Gilbert, 2006).
We think we know why we feel the way we do, so we think we can
predict how we will feel in the future (Gilbert, 2006). The example he provided
was one of the stock market. You expect feel considerably sadder if you make a
bad decision that costs you a thousand dollars than if you sit idly by and
simply fail to make the decision that would realize the gain. But in fact, you
feel sadder from the results of inaction, despite what people predicted
(Kahneman & Tversky, 1982).
For me, the greatest source of regret through inaction is my
failure to practice a musical instrument diligently enough in my youth (aka
before college). I could be so much more capable of expressing myself if I had
put in so much as an hour a day back then. The last time I said this, someone
laughed at the thought of my “youth” being over at 21. And they’re right, I
have plenty of time, especially after graduation when I don’t have overloaded
semesters. But I would prefer to enjoy the benefits now, in the present.
Overall, I feel that Gilbert’s goal was to bring people’s
attention to the fact that their imagination works against their own happiness,
and to provide tools to counteract that. However, he also recognizes the
futility of challenging the millions of years of evolution that have produced a
mind that actively resists using those new tools instead of the tricks it
already knows. The moment of glory (for his recommendations) was over before it
begun. But just because you might imagine no one will take the advice to heart,
doesn’t mean they won’t.
——————————————————
Eyal, T.,
et. al. (2004). The pros and cons of temporally near and distant action. Jouranl of Personality and Social
Psychology, 86, 781–95.
Gilbert,
D. (2006). Stumbling on happiness. New York, NY: Knopf.
Kahneman,
D., & Tversky, A. (1982). The psychology of preferences. Scientific American, 246, (160–74).
McFarland,
C., & Miller, D.T. (1990). Judgments of self-other similarity: Just like
other people, only more so. Personality
and Social Psychology Bulletin, 16, 475–84.
Ross,
L., Greene, D., & House, P. (1977). The false consensus phenomenon: An
attributional bias in self-perception and social-perception processes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
13, 279–301.
Tversky,
A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency
and probability. Cognitive Psychology,
5, 207–232.
It definitely sounds like an interesting book to read, and it seems like you enjoyed it.
ReplyDeleteI liked how you applied what we've learned in Social Psych to the book or maybe you just focused on the stuff in the book that we've been over in class. Overall I liked it.
I feel this would be a book I may be interested in based on your review.
You said that Gilbert states that our imagination is in our way of our happiness and there are three main errors of imagination: realism, presentism, and rationalization. I like how you gave some personal example. That being said you also mentioned Gilbert gave techniques to overcome these errors, but you didn't really give any. It would also been nice if you had maybe applied one or two of those techniques in something you have done or could do.
Overall though I thought your review of this book was good, interesting, and helpful.
I liked this review a lot! I'm sure Gilbert is really interesting and hilarious to read.
ReplyDeleteI'm interested to hear why we evolved this way of imagining the future which is so clearly ineffective. I'd think that our ability to predict outcomes accurately would be selected for and therefore we'd be really good at it, but I guess that is not the case at all. Perhaps it is because the type of information that is related to the future that we try to predict nowadays is so different than what our ancestors had to think about that it just doesn't work for us modern humans? Huh.
Anyway, about the universal imagination heuristic, I feel like I definitely experience that pretty often. For example, before going to work (as a restaurant server) I am sometimes just thinking, "Oh it'll be great, I'll get to run around and make money and my customers will like me!" And while those things are basically always true, I just also, for whatever reason, tend not to think of how stressful work is in the moment until I'm in the moment and wondering, "Why did I sign up for this?" So I definitely experience that heuristic to some degree.
Anyway, your book sounded very interesting and I may read it soon as my book was also related to happiness and I would love to get more perspectives on what contributes to individual's happiness and well-being! Great review!